One of the more promising-seeming attempts to me was something I thought I might term "ontological ethics." That is, when a morally ambivalent situation arose, I could look to a pre-existing statement about my identity, about who I was, to guide me. This is, I think, something of the thinking behind the mission statements or identity statements that some organizations write. They hope to be guided in tough times by a statement of identity. Many have argued that this was what made Johnson and Johnson's highly ethical reaction to the 1982 Tylenol scare so admirable and why the company enjoyed such a good reputation afterwards.
I saw an example from literature I thought might provide a model. Well, only sort of from literature. It was Jean Valjean from Les Miserables, but I was primarily thinking of the Valjean from the musical, not the Hugo novel. That's because the primary ethical test Valjean faces in the musical is one he puts in rather pointed and ontological terms.
I confess. I like musicals
If you've forgotten, the context is this: Valjean was a criminal who was released on parole. He broke his parole and became a wealthy factory owner and mayor, but the obsessive inspector Javert is determined to find Valjean. He believes he has found him in the mayor, but is unable to coax Valjean to reveal his true identity. Javert lays a trap for Valjean: he lets Valjean think that he has found a man Javert believes to be Valjean, and that Javert intends to send this innocent man to prison for life.
Valjean gives serious thought to letting the man go to prison. He is not without good reasons:
I am the master of hundreds of workers
They all look to me.
Can I abandon them, how would they live,
If I am not free?
If I speak, I am condemned,
If I stay silent, I am damned.
From a utilitarian standpoint, Valjean is probably better off letting the other man take the fall for him. It's a difficult time for working folks, and Valjean is a benevolent factory owner. His arrest and the loss of all he has built will probably mean empty stomachs for many children dependent on the wages his workers earn. From a "greatest good for the greatest number" reckoning, Valjean should shut his damn mouth.
But Valjean has decided before this particular ethical dilemma that he is not ruled by utilitarian choices. He was saved by an idealistic decision made by a priest that was the antithesis of utilitarian thinking. Therefore, Valjean determines that:
My soul belongs to God, I know
I made that bargain long ago
He gave me hope when hope was gone,
He gave me strength to carry on...
Who am I? Who am I?
I'm Jean Valjean.
That's great, but maybe a little too neat
I was very attracted to this resolution Valjean arrived at by applying an ontological solution. It seemed incredibly profound. But maybe a little too profound. This resolution was kind of a contrived and stacked solution. Of course he's able to answer his dilemma by simply answering the question of who he is: that literally is the question. Try to think of a single ethical dilemma you've faced where simply determining who you literally are so easily resolves the problem. I bet you've never faced such a thing.
(Side note: I'm probably misusing the term "ontological." Although ontology is the branch of philosophy that deals with being, I think it's more concerned with fundamental questions of existence, like what it means to exist and how we can know if something really exists. Questions like "who am I?" are more personal questions asked in modernity, and are more pop psychology than philosophy. A Google search reveals only a very moderate use of the term "ontological ethics," and if it were a more philosophically valid term, I imagine it would have a lot more currency. I don't see anyone using the term in the way I meant it twenty years ago.)
Three levels of a similar dilemma
Let's say you're a Marine, sworn to uphold the Constitution against all enemies, foreign and domestic. In scenario one, you are a corporal ordered to lead your squad up a hill, and you believe the attempt will fail and you will all die without serving any useful purpose in the defeat. In scenario two, you are a General ordered by the Pentagon to carry out a strategy you believe will be ineffective and lead to many more deaths on both sides of the war than an effective strategy might. In scenario three, you are the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs, and you are being told to plan and prosecute a war you know the President has rigged evidence in order to start. It's an unjust war, you believe, but one the President feels needs to be fought for larger geo-political ends that justify the means.
The Corporal
As a corporal taking the hill, you aren't being asked to do an ideologically unethical thing (assuming the conflict you are in has passed whatever just war tests you apply to it--you're here, after all, so I assume you believe in the war on some level). You're being asked to do an unethical thing from a utilitarian or practical standpoint. Sacrificing lives for a cause is noble; doing it for nothing is stupid and unethical. Of course, there are possible complications. You might be wrong. Maybe the officers know something you don't know. Maybe they're counting on you to lead your squad so well you accomplish the impossible. Maybe this bad choice is the least bad choice they have.
You could refuse if you're sure the plan is bad and will kill people for nothing. But then you'd go to the brig, and someone else more enthusiastic about following bad plans will take your place. You could follow it out fully and hope for the best, but then you'd be the one who has to live with dead Marines and thinking you could have done something to help them.
There are also alternatives that try to avoid the worst effects of either choice, a Captain Kirk-like searching for the choice that avoids the no-win scenario: You could pretend to carry out the orders with alacrity, but find all kinds of procedural reasons to slow-roll the plan. You could hope that if you slow-roll it long enough, it will get cancelled.
Valjean himself ends up with a mixed response. He turns himself in, but when Javert will not give him three days to wrap up his affairs, Valjean clocks him and escapes again.
The General
The General is in an incredibly tough spot. His objection to his orders is in a murky area between ideological objections and practical ones. He could refuse his orders. As a General, he may be able to simply retire, and he could then write an op-ed in retirement about why he thinks the war is being handled wrong. But again, it's likely someone else will take his place who is a lot more gung-ho about carrying out what he thinks is a broken plan.
He has many of the same half-measure options the corporal does. He could carry out his orders according to the letter of the law, but refuse them in spirit. He could find dozens of subtle ways to undermine the strategy. He could use his position on-the-ground to slightly alter his tactical orders from what the Pentagon wanted. If he does it well, he might alleviate some of the worst parts of the Pentagon's plans. If he just quits, his influence will be limited to whatever credence the public gives to his post-service testimony.
The Chairman
The Chairman's position is the most problematic. He has the most evidence of a clear, idealistic moral wrong, but he also has the most leverage to be able to mitigate the effects of the wrong. He could, of course, quit his job, take his case to the public, and hope the court of public opinion vindicated him. But what if the President, in spite of fighting a war against his objections, rather likes the Chairman and takes his opinion seriously? What if the Chairman, by staying at his post, can at least change the kind of war America fights, if not the raw fact that there is a war? Should he give up his best shot at influencing the situation in order to make a point?
What all three quandaries have in common
None of these moral dilemmas can be solved by applying the Valjean test. You can't say "Who am I?" and come up with an answer that will point you in the direction of a solution.
But maybe there is something similar that could be useful
If you've ever taken a multiple choice test, you're probably familiar with the strategy of answering the same thing to two different questions, because you know it's the right answer to one of them, and you figure it's better to know you're getting one of two right rather than take a chance of missing them both.
While I don't think real life offers us many instances where we can just ask ourselves who we really are and get a useful answer to a moral question, it's possible that we can develop a heuristic that will at least limit our possible errors. It's a different question from "Who am I?" It's "If I have to make a mistake, what kind of mistake would I rather make?" For the corporal, for example, his possible mistakes are: 1) Stand up for the safety of his troops and be wrong that the mission was really doomed, or 2) Err on the side of following orders, and find out that his suspicions were correct, and his Marines died without accomplishing anything discernible.
To use an example more common to many of us, let's say someone is asking us for money. We suspect they're scamming us, but there's maybe a twenty percent chance the story we're getting is real. Is it worse to trust someone and be a sucker or to doubt someone and miss a chance to help?
If we decide for ourselves what kinds of mistakes most suit who we are, and we stick to making those kinds of mistakes, we may not improve our chances of getting it right in any one situation. We might, however, limit the types of mistakes we are likely to make over the long term. Assuming that out of 1,000 truly difficult decisions, one type of action or the other is likely to be the right one in about 500 of them, we can, by being consistent, be right at least 500 times. And we'll find it easier, perhaps, to have failed on our own terms. Changing the kind of mistake we're willing to risk making with each situation, however, makes it possible we will be wrong more than half the time. (It also makes it possible we'll be right more than half the time, but do you want to take those odds?) It can also leave us bitter when we make choices that don't suit our own inner voices.
Still not sure this is satisfying
I don't know if twenty-some years of pontificating on this has led me to a more satisfying solution than I started out with. For one thing, it's possible there are some people with such a developed ability to weigh outcomes, they really can make the correct decision more than half the time. I wouldn't want to preclude people from making decisions differently from one situation to the next if they can really do it well. For me, though, I tend to be so often paralyzed by tough choices I almost just never even make them. At least having some rough algorithm might get me to make the decisions.
If God does not exist, there are no objectively "right" or "wrong" answers, nor even answers that are objectively closer to being right or wrong. There's just what *you* happen to value, and since we all naturally gravitate to our own preferences, what you do will be aligned most closely with your own values. If God doesn't exist, subjective preferences are the closest we can get to final answers on ethics.
ReplyDeleteIf God does exist, then every ethical question boils down to the question, "Who is God? What does He value?"
But I would say that all ethical questions, and answers, are by nature "ontological" - they all deal with the ultimate nature of being, which is related to purpose: Why do we consider it wrong to sacrifice young lives for a cause that doesn't justify the loss? They're all going to die eventually anyway, as will we all. Premature death is tragic because we all have a sense of what a life is *supposed* to be -- i.e., a sense of purpose to life itself, which extends down to individual lives -- and premature death averts that purpose.
I don't necessarily think that ethics being subjective makes them meaningless. Bertrand Russell argued that ethics are, of course, subjective. Proving something is right comes down to your ability to convince others of the rightness of you ethical viewpoint.
DeleteThat's terrifying, but there's also something comforting in that. Ethical actions are the actions that I think are most likely to result in a world that I want to live in. That doesn't involve arguing from fact, like in a math problem, but arguing from a sense of beauty. Ethics are what lead to the most beautiful outcome. Seen like this, all ethics aren't ontological, they're aesthetic.
I realize it's unsatisfying for ethics to be subjective. That means figuring out what's right is a lot messier than it would be in a system of absolute ethical values. But that's really just admitting to the complexity that is already there. I can't pretend I believe in a God who sets out ultimate standards just because it would be comforting to believe in one.
And theism doesn't really seem to settle problems in the ethical realm. Christians argued throughout the 18th and 19th century about whether God approved of slavery. Advocates could point to "Slaves, obey your masters." Abolitionists could point to "In Christ there is neither slave nor free." Pro-war Christians and pacifist Christians--thoughtful people on both sides--can both make a compelling case that their view on war is what Christianity really calls for.
So I don't really see an alternative to ethics as a subjective science, and I'm not entirely sure that the subjectivity of ethics means it's meaningless.
Just to be clear -- we're agreed that morality (not necessarily ethics, but morality) is subjective. The question is whether it is *merely* subjective, or if our individual subjective moralities are ultimately measured against an absolute, universal and transcendent ethical standard.
DeleteIf they are *merely* subjective, then yes -- that means they are, ultimately, meaningless. There is no *actual* "right" or "wrong." Morality isn't *immediately* meaningless, but that meaning doesn't extend beyond subjective preferences.
Your second paragraph simply doesn't work. The Nazis certainly had a different sense of beauty than you and I have, and wanted to live in a world that would have been completely different from the one we want.
Would you say their ideal for the world they wanted to live in was better or worse than ours? And was it *actually* worse, or just "worse" in the sense that it's not what we happen to prefer? If the Nazis had won and managed to conquer the whole earth, leaving no one alive who didn't share their view, would they still be wrong?
Theism does not purport to "settle problems" in the ethical realm. Theism is the entire reason we have ethical questions in the first place. You're talking about "ethical questions" as if there are answers to be arrived at that are actually right or wrong. But if no one is grading the test, why do the answers matter?
You're committing, I think, a common error with regard to the Moral Argument. The Moral Argument is often presented (by theists and non-theists alike) as "We need God (or a belief in God), otherwise no one will be moral." Some even present it as the even worse argument of, "We need the Bible or we won't know right from wrong."
No, the Moral Argument (as Paul made it in Romans 2:14, 15) is that we all *already* have a moral compass -- we *already* know, in our very bones, that there is a real difference between right and wrong, and we are accountable to live by it. But accountable to whom? If our internal sense of right and wrong ultimately means anything, there has to be an Authority greater than man -- greater than any government, any tribal group, any cultural pressure or any other merely human set of standards and obligations. Otherwise, we have no real basis for pressing any moral claim, or for condemning the Nazis or 19th-century slave traders on the grounds of, "You ought to have known better, because you have the same internal moral sense as the rest of humanity ... "
Regarding slavery and the Bible ... I agree that the debate was had among Christians, but if we were to read the Bible ourselves on its own terms, as dispassionate outsiders with no economic or cultural stake in the argument, we'd find that the Bible -- from beginning to end, but particularly in the Mosaic law -- is a recipe to end slavery.
As you know, Jews and Christians didn't invent slavery. Slavery has existed as long as humanity has, universally, in every culture on Earth. It was Jews and Christians who ended it, though. And why? Because it's what the Bible teaches ...
But, that's a different discussion, and the Moral Argument doesn't revolve around the Bible being inspired or authoritative. We could remove the Bible and Christianity and even the very concept of divine revelation from the equation entirely, and we'd still have the Moral Argument to contend with.
First, regarding Christianity and ethics. I don't see the practical difference between God having a standard that Christians seem to have a hard time figuring out and ethics just being something humans realize is subjective and we have to work out for ourselves. To use slavery as an example (which I don't use to hammer Christianity for its hypocrisy so much as because it should have been something relatively easy to figure out--God could have just said "slavery is wrong"), it took 1800 years and the bloodiest war in American history for American Christians to decided that slavery was wrong. And that was after Western, Christian society created the first global market of slavery which extended the scale of suffering to an extent never before seen. Yes, Christians didn't invent slavery. But they perfected it.
DeleteYour qualification of people who read the bible"on its own terms, as dispassionate outsiders with no economic or cultural stake in the argument" being able to find the right answers is essentially saying nobody will ever get the right answers. Yes, Christians did argue for the end of slavery. A small percentage of Christians, who were mostly seen as annoying and fringe, were abolitionists. Those same 19th-century reformers were often also anti-alcohol and anti-war. Do you agree with them on these points, too? I'd say the argument for being a pacifist is as strong from the Bible as the argument against slavery. Which is to say, it's there if you want to see it, and not there if you don't.
I have to conclude, since God didn't give clear instructions on so many issues, that if He did, indeed, write the Bible, He wrote it in such a way that humans were free to answer these questions for themselves. And I'm fine doing that.
So what does this mean for your question about the Nazis? Were they Wrong with a capital "W"? Or just wrong according to my own personal tastes?
Humans naturally have empathy, like a lot of mammals. Rats demonstrate it. We evolved that way. The Nazis violated human understanding of empathy. So it was possible for humans who were and were not of a Judeo-Christian background to be horrified by what the Nazis did. We are born with a morality by our biology, not by God. As humans, we are able to think abstractly about good and evil more than rats, and we can have complicated thoughts about what is good and bad. But I think these are extrapolations from our biological impulses, not insight into the divine mind.
Private morality is always complicated when it has to be turned into public ethics, because what works privately may not always work "at scale." "Turn the other cheek," for example, might be bad policy for a government. The Nazis were arguing that our natural empathy for the Jews was bad, because it hurt the state. Most people disagreed, even, probably, many actual Nazis who went along because they felt they had to. (I'd wager this included some Christian Nazis.) The Nazis were wrong because in the main, their subjugation of private morality to public ethics felt wrong to the moral compasses of most people. That's it. It didn't violate any Platonic ideals of right and wrong. It was wrong because humans felt it was wrong--enough that we were able to fight against it and win.